Surname
Course name and number
Instructor’s name
University affiliation
Date submitted
The topic for Paper 2: Metaethics
• Is there a non-relative
(objective) morality?
Non-elative (objective) morality exists. Moore(351) stated that basic
moral judgments convey goodness or badness to the realities of things, albeit
he preferred not to separate moral ideas and moral standards in Principia
Ethica. Like many of his contemporaries, he appears to believe that moral judgments
are objectively true. Also, basic moral
principles are universal and rational individuals may agree on their veracity.
But moral relativism is the only viable counter-argument. Moral relativism is
justified by the fact that various cultures have varying standards for
measuring right and wrong. In general, however, even the most complicated moral
decisions can be broken down into a few fundamental elements, which are then
adapted to the particular material circumstances of each society. However, the
fact that various communities form moral judgments differently does not imply
relativism. A relativist must demonstrate that civilizations do not share basic
moral judgments to justify their argument. Neither of these ideas has been
fulfilled.
While society's moral practices may vary, the basic moral concepts do
not. James Rachels describes the culture in "Morality Is Not
Relative". Cultural relativism states that there are no established moral
norms since different cultures have different beliefs about values. Rachel, for
example, illustrates his point by citing other people's lives. Rachel brings up
a seldom-mentioned issue of Eskimos killing babies. As Rachel points out,
Eskimo women regularly murder their female children after delivery, and they do
it without showing any emotion in the process. Meta-ethics should not hinder
the pragmatic objective of finding direction for human social interaction based
on what is a shared human nature. Many have tried to impose their morals
on others, including Hitler, Stalin, and
Mao Zedong. It is also true that
none of our great moral instructors ever created their morality. As an
illustration, Jesus didn't invent a new moral code, but instead, he refined and
expanded upon the existing one. Even
objective moral norms are shaped by the society and epoch in which they are
embodied. For example, a man (even a chief) has never been able to choose his
bride (as far as we know). In Britain, women must be above sixteen, although
this varies by country. What matters is that the objective moral principle is
followed. No more than we can develop new basic color.
• Are ethical claims accurate or
untrue (and why)? If so, how much do you agree with moral nihilists and/or
non-cognitivists?
Humans have a shared sense of intuition, hence ethical claims are true.
Our understanding of moral truths is intuitive, according to Moore (351-352),
because it does not depend on reasoning from non-moral ideas, but rather relies
on the recognition of specific moral statements that are self-evident, as
a result of a form of direct or instantaneous insight. Suffering and theft are
both morally wrong. This is a self-evident, plain reality about life. Stealing
is wrong, even if you like it and even if you fool others into thinking it
isn't. Intuitively, these ethical facts are objective: their reality does not
change depending on one's position or choices. Moral propositions like these
are objectively accurate, according to ethical realists like Moore(351).
Realists think there are correct ethical responses.
However, realists and anti-realists alike seem to think Moore's Open
Question Argument captures something significant about moral assertions that
nonmoral claims cannot (352). According to logical Positivists, moral
assertions are intrinsically linked to motivation in a manner that nonmoral
statements are not (Ayer 328). The relationship to motivation is contested, but
one prevalent argument (motivation internalism) is that an individual may only
make a genuine moral claim if she is adequately motivated. Goodness comes from
being in favor of something in ways that offer some motive (not necessarily
decisive) to promote, develop, maintain or otherwise support it. People tend to
presume someone who lacks such incentives yet professes to believe the subject
in issue is excellent is either being dishonest or not understanding what she
is saying. Unlike nonmoral assertions, which appear to imply nothing about the
claimant's intentions. This is immaterial to whether or not her assertion that
objects have that hue is honest and widely understood. Moral realism is based
on a cognitivist interpretation of moral judgments. Moral judgments, like
ordinary beliefs, are cognitive states for cognitivism. But how do we know? One
approach is to think about what we want to accomplish when we make moral
judgments, as well as how we say them. In the same way that statements
communicate ordinary ideas, moral judgments are designed to accurately describe
reality. In other words, moral expression is expressed through ethical statements.
Moral judgments, like ordinary beliefs, are either true or false.
• Is egoism true (and how much)?
Can humans act without self-interest (and how do we know)?
Yes, egoism exists. Depending on one's needs and self-realization.
Friedrich Nietzsche's theory has been related to descriptive and normative
egoism. The moral abhorrence for egoistic activity is attacked by Nietzsche to
liberate higher human beings from the notion that it is beneficial for them.
Other egoistic viewpoints exist alongside psychological egoism. Psychological
egoism, unlike ethical egoism, is an empirical argument about our intentions,
not what they should be. This is why, in contrast to the ethical egoist, the
psychological egoist thinks that humans are naturally self-interested.
Psychological egoism is not the same as "psychological hedonism."
Psychological hedonism limits self-interested drives to pleasure and pain
avoidance. It is therefore a kind of psychological egoism. Psychological
egoism's origin narrative is odd. Though constantly debated, few prominent
thinkers in philosophy's history have officially held it.
However, Stirner emphasizes that
an egoist might be moral without egoism (Welsh & ProQuest (Firm), 2010).
Stirner says morality is OK as long as the egoist controls it rather than the
other way around (Welsh & ProQuest (Firm), 2010). His fundamental thesis is
that individuals should act according to their interests, not regulations. As
long as the rules do not dominate the individual, they are operating as an egoist.
In contrast, one who calls himself or herself a "moral egoist" is
placing norms above self-interest, which is a big no-no. A moral compass is
contradictory to egoism, hence the egoist should not use one. Embodiment in
so-called morality does not enable the egoist to escape the consequences of his
actions (Welsh & ProQuest (Firm), 2010). Any guilt someone feels should be
felt, and there should be no Supreme Directive allowing him to escape the
repercussions of his actions. Stirner recognized that abusers constantly
justify their actions as ethically good. Egoism eliminates the
get-out-of-condemnation card, forcing the egoist to reveal his motivations
honestly.
In general, what can we learn
about ethics from descriptive assertions about biology (or brains or institutions
or emotions)?
What we can learn from ethics is that they assist us to define our moral
views while making judgments. The purpose of learning ethics is to get a better
understanding of morality, honesty, accountability, consciousness, decency, dignity,
and respect in a variety of settings. It broadens our horizons and makes us
more contemplative and thoughtful. It helps us think clearly and rationally
about moral matters. The human being is by nature a 'social' being, a being in
contact with other beings and the environment. All activities, whether
conscious or not, affect others. That ethical arguments frequently use
"facts" inside an imagined context/conventions (Ayer 326). Scientists
may draw on a vast corpus of information to make judgments. But much of this
information is based on value judgments, personal goals, and even the
researcher's character and style. Because there are no absolute values, nothing
matters and everything is significant. This is a facile way of saying that you
don't have to make a decision or take a position on the morality of the
situation.
References
Ayer, Alfred. "Language, Truth, And Logic.". The
Journal Of Philosophy, vol 33, no. 12, 1936, p.
328. Philosophy
Documentation Center, https://doi.org/10.2307/2016260.
Moore, George. "Principia
Ethica.". The Philosophical Review, vol 13, no. 3, 1904, p.
351. JSTOR, https://doi.org/10.2307/2176289.
Welsh, John F. Max
Stirner's Dialectical Egoism: A New Interpretation. Lanham, Md: Lexington
Books, 2010. P.
104.
Comments
Post a Comment